Mohon tunggu...
Hireka Eric
Hireka Eric Mohon Tunggu... -

Hello! Keep updated with my posts on Blogger, hirekaeric.blogspot.com

Selanjutnya

Tutup

Filsafat

Bet That God Exists and You Won't Lose: Pascal

17 Januari 2012   19:37 Diperbarui: 25 Juni 2015   20:45 744
+
Laporkan Konten
Laporkan Akun
Kompasiana adalah platform blog. Konten ini menjadi tanggung jawab bloger dan tidak mewakili pandangan redaksi Kompas.
Lihat foto
Bagikan ide kreativitasmu dalam bentuk konten di Kompasiana | Sumber gambar: Freepik

Critique of Pascal’s Wager : An Excerpt

Critique du Pari de Pascal : Un Extrait

Pascal, les Pensées and le Pari

‘The Wager’ (le pari) is a 17th-century pragmatic view on Christianity, proposed by French mathematician, physicist and philosopher Blaise Pascal (1623-1662). Imbued with scepticism, Pascal has long been compared to Kierkegaard ‘as a leading example of religious conviction based on existential commitment and faith rather than on reason’.[1]

The argument of the Wager itself can be found in a chapter of his chef-d’œuvre, Pensées de M. Pascal sur la religion et sur quelques autres sujets (Pascal’s thoughts on religion and some other subjects), posthumously published in 1670.

No uniformity in the arrangement of the Pensées has been achieved—as evidenced by the many different French and translated versions available today.[2] Therefore, it behoves me to convince myself that the following suffice for this brief essay: the French editon (FP) published by Garnier Frères in 1886 and the English version (EP) translated by A.J. Krailsheimer in 1966.

In FP one can find Pascal’s arguments about the Wager on pages 67–72 under the chapter « Qu’il est plus avantageux de croire que de ne pas croire ce qu’enseigne la religion chrétienne » (that it is more advantageous to believe than not to believe what the Christian religion teaches). The English equivalent can be read in EP on pages 149–152, under the chapter ‘The Wager’.

The objective of Pascal’s Wager

Proving the existence of God is not first and foremost the objective of Pascal’s Wager.[3] Rather, it aims at convincing nonbelievers that the belief in God is the ‘best bet’ (Simon Blackburn, 2008:268). This is testified by the notice to the chapter in the Port-Royal edition (Guillaume Desprez, 1670), which reads:

‘Almost everything that is contained in this chapter is concerned only with some kinds of people who, unconvinced of the evidence of religion—let alone reasons of atheists—remain in a state of suspension between faith and infidelity. The author only claims to show them by their own principles, and by the simple light of reason, that they should judge that it is advantageous to them to believe, and that it would be the stand they should take if this choice depended on their will. Hence it follows that at least until they find the light needed to be convinced of the truth, they must do all that incline them towards it, and free themselves from all hitches that divert them from that faith, which primarily are passions and vain amusements.’

« Presque tout ce qui est contenu dans ce chapitre ne regarde que certaines sortes de personnes qui n’étant pas convaincues des preuves de la Religion, et encore moins des raisons des Athées, demeurent en un état de suspension entre la foi et l’infidélité. L’auteur prétend seulement leur montrer par leurs propres principes, et par les simples lumières de la raison, qu’ils doivent juger qu’il leur est avantageux de croire, et que ce serait le parti qu’ils devraient prendre, si ce choix dépendait de leur volonté. D’où il s’ensuit qu’au moins en attendant qu’ils aient trouvé la lumière nécessaire pour se convaincre de la vérité, ils doivent faire tout ce qui les y peut disposer, et se dégager de tous les empêchements qui les détournent de cette foi, qui sont principalement les passions et les vains amusements. »

The thesis and argumentation of Pascal’s Wager

On the basis of the following quotation one can discover the provocative thesis of Pascal’s Wager.

‘Let us weigh up the gain and the loss involved in calling heads that God exists. Let us assess the two cases: if you win you win everything, if you lose you lose nothing. Do not hesitate then; wager that he does exist.’ (EP:151)

« Pesons le gain et la perte, en prenant croix, que Dieu est. Estimons ces deux cas : si vous gagnez, vous gagnez tout; si vous perdez, vous ne perdez rien. Gagez donc qu’il est, sans hésiter. »

(FP:69-70)

In other words, the thesis shall be, ‘Wagering that God exists has always been the best choice because one can win everything but can lose nothing’—that is why the heading of this pensée is ‘Infinity – nothing’ (Infini. Rien.).

Pascal deduced the above-mentioned thesis from the following argumentation (cf. EP:149-151, FP:68-69).

1.He drew a distinction between the extension and the limits of (1) the finite, (2) the infinite and (3) God; and explained how these affect the possibility of human rational knowledge of them.

It has...

By reason we know...

Extension

Limits

Its existence

Its nature

The finite

e.g. human beings

Yes

Yes

Yes

Yes

The infinite

e.g. numbers

Yes

No

Yes

No

God

No

No

No

No

According to Pascal, since God is indivisible and without limits, we do not bear any relation to him. Thus, neither the existence nor the nature of God can be known by reason: ‘We are therefore incapable of knowing either what he is or whether he is.’[4]

2.It is given that ‘Either God is or he is not’ (Dieu est, ou il n’est pas). Since reason cannot decide this question, nor can it prove either wrong, one must wager in this necessary game—he cannot choose not to wager at all.

3.One must stake both his reason/knowledge and will/happiness on whether God exists. He has to avoid error and wretchedness lest he loses the true and the good.[5] What option, then, should he wager on?

4.Here comes the above-mentioned thesis, which may well be illustrated by the following table.

God exists

God does not exist

Wager for God

Infinite reward (+∞)

Status quo (finite)

Wager against God

Infinite punishment (-∞)

Status quo (finite)

Arguments for Pascal’s Wager

The table testifies to the argument from superdominance, which concludes that whether God is or he is not, wagering for God always leads to a result that is better than or at least the same as wagering against God. Alan Hájek (2011) puts it:

‘Wagering for God superdominates wagering against God: the worst outcome associated with wagering for God (status quo) is at least as good as the best outcome associated with wagering against God (status quo); and if God exists, the result of wagering for God is strictly better that the result of wagering against God. [...] Pascal draws the conclusion at this point that rationality requires you to wager for God.’

It should be noticed that this argument requires that the decision be made under uncertainty, which means that ‘the agent does not assign subjective probabilities to the states of the world’ (Hájek, 2011).

If such decision is made under risk, i.e. the agent does assign subjective probabilities, one will deal with the argument from expectations. Under this argument, ‘the expected utility of an outcome is the utility that is assigned to its occurrence, multiplied by the probability of its occurrence’.[6] Accordingly, the preference for wagering for God remains the same because its expected utility is still larger than wagering against God. Suppose that there is a 50:50 chance that God exists and figure 1 denotes the finite value of status quo.[7] The expectation of each wage will be:

wagering for God = ½(+∞) + ½(1) = +

wagering against God = ½(-∞) + ½(1) = -

As long as God’s existence has a finite probability (e.g. ½, ¼, or else), its expected utility will always be positively infinite and thus overtake other outcomes, even if the probability assigned to it is very small—this is what is called the argument from dominating expectations. Hence it is rational to believe in God.

Apart from the perspective of decision theory, Pascal’s Wager can be supported on grounds of pragmatism. American psychologist and philosopher William James (1842-1910) in his 1897 lecture “The Will to Believe” argues that the utility of the resulting states of mind can determine what one believes. Therefore, believing in God is legitimate because it has beneficial effects on the believer, regardless of the evidence given to them.[8]

Arguments against Pascal’s Wager

Throughout history, quite a few philosophers have objected to this particular notion of Pascal. For instance, Voltaire (1694-1778) remarked on it:

‘It is a very false assertion, that the not laying a wager that God exists, is laying that he does not exist: for certainly that man whose mind is in a state of doubt, and is desirous of being informed, assuredly does not lay on either side; moreover this article is really indecent and childish: the idea of gaming, of losing and winning, is quite unsuitable to the dignity of the subject: farther, the interest I have to believe a thing is no proof that such a thing exists.’ (Voltaire, 1763)

« Il est évidemment faux de dire: Ne point parier que Dieu est, c’est parier qu’il n’est pas; car celui qui doute et demande à s’éclaircir ne parie assurément ni pour ni contre. D’ailleurs, cet article parait un peu indécent et puéril; cette idée de jeu, de perte et de gain, ne convient point à la gravité du sujet; de plus l’intérêt que j’ai à croire une chose n’est pas une preuve de l’existence de cette chose. »

(Voltaire, 1728)

However, Voltaire seems to have mistakenly believed that Pascal wanted to prove the existence of God by the Wager argument—he did not. Further, by rejecting all the idea of wagering since the beginning, Voltaire did not actually contribute to the arguments against the wager (Hájek, 2011).

Putting aside the meticulous calculation of probability and the decision theory, I would like to take a more existentialist point of view. First, can doubtful people be persuaded to whole-heartedly believe in God only with this argument? Does a decision to believe automatically lead to the will to believe? Paul Saka (2005) proposes an interesting illustration: ‘If I offered to pay you $1000 for believing the sky is green, for instance, could you sincerely adopt this belief simply by wishing to?’ It is obvious then that belief is not merely a matter of deliberate decision, but rather of heart, of will.[9] Did Pascal himself not write that ‘the heart has its reasons, which reason does not know’ (Le cœur a ses raisons que la raison ne connoît point)?

Second, Pascal did not take into account the many possibilities of the nature of God. Since he asserted that no one knew of the nature of God, is it impossible that there existed a God who favours genuineness and strongly disapproves of insincerity? Which of these two persons would God reward with infinite bliss: an atheist who, out of his self-awareness, leads a morally good life without even thinking of God, or a religious fanatic who believes in God lest he is not condemned to eternal punishment?

Bibliography

Primary Sources

Pascal, Blaise. Pensées de Pascal sur la religion et sur quelques autres sujets. Paris: Garnier Frères (first published in 1866).

Pascal, Blaise. Pensées, trans. A.J. Krailsheimer. London: Penguin Books, 1970 (first published in 1966).

Secondary Sources

Blackburn, Simon. The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press, 2008 (second edition revised).

Desprez, Guillaume (ed.). Pensées de M. Pascal sur la religion et sur quelques autres sujets, qui ont esté trouvées après sa mort parmy ses papiers, Édition de Port-Royal, second edition, 1670 (modernised orthography). http://fr.wikisource.org/wiki/Pens%C3%A9es/%C3%89dition_de_Port-Royal.

Hájek, Alan. ‘Pascal’s Wager’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2011/entries/pascal-wager/ (last modified on 17 June 2011).

Hardiman, F. Budi. Filsafat Modern: Dari Machiavelli sampai Nietzsche. Jakarta: Gramedia Pustaka Utama, 2004.

Saka, Paul. ‘Pascal’s Wager about God’, The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://www.iep.utm.edu/pasc-wag/ (last modified on 20 April 2005).

Voltaire. ‘Remarques (Premières) sur les Pensées de Pascal (1728)’. L’Association Voltaire Intégral. http://www.voltaire-integral.com/Html/22/07_Pascal.html

Voltaire. The Works of M. de Voltaire with Notes, Historical and Critical, Vol. XXVI, trans. Tobias George Smollett and Thomas Francklin. London: 1763. http://books.google.co.id/books?id=JDcLAAAAQAAJ.

[1] Simon Blackburn (2006), p. 268.

[2] A.J. Krailsheimer (EP:27) wrote, ‘A translator of Pascal must pick one edition and stick to it; he will only make confusion worse confounded by introducing editorial variants of his own. At present there are more than half a dozen different arrangements of the Pensées on sale, and the number is not likely to diminish. So many different numberings exist that checking one version against another has become an intolerable chore, and none commands universal assent.’

[3] F. Budi Hardiman (2004), p.63. ‘Argumen le pari ini sebetulnya tidak dimaksudkan Pascal sendiri untuk membuktikan ada tidaknya Allah. Yang dia tuju sebetulnya adalah sekelompok orang yang tidak percaya kepada agama Kristen.

[4] « Nous sommes donc incapables de connoître ni ce qu’il est, ni s’il est. »

[5] « Voyons, puisqu’il faut choisir, voyons ce qui vous intéresse le moins : vous avez deux choses à perdre, le vrai et le bien, et deux choses à engager, votre raison et votre volonté, votre connoissance et votre béatitude ; et votre nature a deux choses à fuir, l’erreur et la misère. »

[6] Blackburn, p. 125.

[7] Cf. Paul Saka (2005).

[8] Blackburn, p. 387.

[9] Pascal’s heart may be seen as a will. Cf. Hardiman, p. 60. ‘Kadang-kadang Pascal menyejajarkan hati dengan “kehendak” yang berkaitan dengan “kepercayaan”.’

HALAMAN :
  1. 1
  2. 2
  3. 3
  4. 4
  5. 5
Mohon tunggu...

Lihat Konten Filsafat Selengkapnya
Lihat Filsafat Selengkapnya
Beri Komentar
Berkomentarlah secara bijaksana dan bertanggung jawab. Komentar sepenuhnya menjadi tanggung jawab komentator seperti diatur dalam UU ITE

Belum ada komentar. Jadilah yang pertama untuk memberikan komentar!
LAPORKAN KONTEN
Alasan
Laporkan Konten
Laporkan Akun